상세 컨텐츠

본문 제목

The Realms Of Being Santayana Pdf Reader

카테고리 없음

by omnanrikil1973 2020. 2. 14. 09:01

본문

This article needs additional citations for. Unsourced material may be challenged and removed. (January 2014) The Life of Reason, subtitled 'the Phases of Human Progress', is a book published in five volumes from 1905 to 1906, by Spanish-born American philosopher (1863–1952). It consists of Reason in Common Sense, Reason in Society, Reason in Religion, Reason in Art, and Reason in Science. The work is considered to be the most complete expression of Santayana's; by contrast, his later magnum opus, the four-volume, more fully develops his and theory, particularly his doctrine of essences.

Santayana's philosophy is strongly influenced by the of and the refined ethics of, with a special emphasis on the natural development of ideal ends. The Life of Reason is sometimes considered to be one of the most poetic and well-written works of philosophy in Western history.

To supply but a single example, the oft-quoted of Santayana's, 'Those who cannot remember the past are condemned to repeat it,' may be found on p. 284 of Reason in Common Sense. In 1951, near the end of his life, Santayana engaged himself in the weighty task of producing a one-volume abridgment of The Life of Reason at the urging of his editor at Scribner's, with the assistance of his friend and student, Daniel Cory. As Cory writes in the volume's preface, in addition to excising prolixities and redundancies from the book, 'a sustained effort was made to dispel those early mists of idealism from the realistic body of his philosophy, and to make clear to the reader that our idea of a natural world can never be that world itself.' Contents.

Volumes Reason in Society Santayana wishes, according to, to 'devise a means whereby men may be persuaded to virtue without the stimulus of supernatural hopes and fears.' Unfortunately, as he says in 'Reason in Society', 'a truly rational morality or social regimen has never existed in the world, and is hardly to be looked for' as such constructions are the luxury of philosophers. The non-philosopher must rely upon the 'growth of those social emotions which bloom in the generous atmosphere of love and the home.' He agrees with that, in love, 'nine-tenths of the cause of love are in the lover, for one-tenth that may be in the object' and that love 'fuses the soul again into the impersonal blind flux.' Despite this, he still champions love as the most fulfilling experience of life: ' is reported to have said on his deathbed that science was mere trifling, and that nothing was real but love.'

Families and children are immensely important too, as, 'we commit the blotted manuscript of our lives more willingly to the flames, when we find the immortal text half engrossed in a fairer copy.' Though families provide the basic unit of organization among men, it is necessary to develop beyond them. For this, he advocates a sort of, for though the state is 'a monster,' he accepts its necessity in maintaining stability and safety for its constituents. This 'natural aristocracy' (a term never used by Santayana; taken instead from ) is built upon Santayana's dislike of equality—he argues, with, that 'the equality of unequals is inequality'—though he still champions. Moreover, Santayana distrusts, and sees it as 'a vulgar, anonymous tyranny,' much like Plato.

His society would be, roughly, a in which the most competent and capable would govern, with all men and women possessing an open road to government: 'The only equality subsisting would be equality of opportunity.' In a phrase anticipating, Santayana says: 'but for the excellence of the typical single life no nation deserves to be remembered more than the sands of the sea;' indeed, in Rawls notes that ' the natural aristocracy of Santayana is a possible interpretation of the two principles of justice,' though he ultimately rejects such a conception in favour of. Santayana advocates such a mix of and democracy, and believes that under such a system art and science would flourish, and corruption be minimized.

Corruption abounds in common governments, which often become a vehicle for war, the worst of all crimes of the state. Over- too is abject to him, and he sees it responsible for many of the crimes of the state. Though he proposes no philosophy of international relations, he muses that the development of international sports could provide something of 'a moral equivalent for war' and that finance and trade between nations may help foster more peace between them. At last, he laments the rise of industrialism; quoting Emerson: 'things are in the saddle and ride mankind.' Leisure is critically important to a society, and necessary for the development of culture and arts, since 'civilization has hitherto consisted in the diffusion and dilution of habits arising in privileged centers.'

The and the dream of 'laissez-faire industrialism' is a lie, and is responsible for the endless struggles of modern man. Reason in Religion Though a philosophical, Santayana is often described as an aesthetic. Influenced by his Spanish Roman Catholic heritage, he laments his own loss of, calling religious (especially Catholic) belief a 'splendid error, which conforms better to the impulses of the ' than life. Durant says he: 'achieves his masterpiece in 'Reason in Religion', filling his skeptical pages with a tender sadness, and finding in the beauty of Catholicism plentiful cause for loving it still.' Santayana scorns the harsh treatment of religion by many 'worm-eaten old satirists,' and emphasizes the importance of understanding religion for understanding man, since religion is common to all men.

Institute Of Education Sciences

With the touch of a poet, he lauds the beauty of religious while condemning literal treatment of religion to the flames. He especially derides the 'northern barbarians' who are responsible for, and believes they are mostly responsible for its literal interpretation and the loss of Christianity's poetry.

Reason in Science Santayana holds that bases itself on science, as 'science contains all trustworthy knowledge.' Though he acknowledges the limitations of science and reason in finding metaphysical truths, he holds the scientific method as 'merely a shorthand description of regularities observed in our experience' and says in 'Reason in Common Sense': 'faith in the intellect.is the only faith yet sanctioned by its fruits.' Proposing no technically new metaphysic, Santayana instead applies old philosophies to the modern day. He admires the of and emphasis upon technically reason of. Santayana is a and a, and strongly dislikes the more mystical metaphysics of many of his contemporaries; he rejects even the of, saying that 'the word nature is poetical enough; it suggest sufficiently the generative and controlling function, the endless vitality and changeful order of the world in which I live.'

Materialism and mechanism are the governing forces of the universe; there is nothing outside their laws, and nothing exempt—humans included. Staying true to this materialism, Santayana rejects the existence of a transcendent, instead positing that 'the soul is only a fine quick organization within the material animal.' He also rejects immortality in the common sense of the word, saying in: 'I believe there is nothing immortal.No doubt the spirit and energy of the world is what is acting in us, as the sea is what rises in every little wave; but it passes through us; and, cry out as we may, it will move on.

Idealism

Our privilege is to have perceived it as it moved.' He does, however, espouse an unorthodox, Spinozist view of immortality: “ He who lives in the ideal and leaves it expressed in society or in art enjoys a double immortality. The eternal has absorbed him while he lived, and when he is dead his influence brings others to the same absorption, making them, through that ideal identity with the best in him, reincarnations and perennial seats of all in him which he could rationally hope to rescue from destruction. He can say, without any subterfuge or desire to delude himself, that he shall not wholly die; for he will have a better notion than the vulgar of what constitutes his being. By becoming the spectator and confessor of his own death and of universal mutation, he will have identified himself with what is spiritual in all spirits and masterful in all apprehension; and so conceiving himself, he may truly feel and know that he is eternal. — Reason in Religion, pg. 273 ” Bibliography.

Reader

Reason in Common Sense, 1905. Reason in Society, 1905. Reason in Religion, 1905. Reason in Art, 1905. Reason in Science, 1906 Notes. George Santayana, 'Later Soliloquies' (1922), p.

Materialism

253: 'Was it, I wonder, this touch of sympathy with splendid error, bred in me by long familiarity with religion and philosophy, that offended my honest critics? Now that I show less sympathy with it, will they be better satisfied? I fear the opposite is the case. What they resented was rather that in spite of all my sympathy, and of all my despair about science, it never occurred to me to think those errors true, because they were splendid, except true to the soul. Did they expect that I should seriously debate whether the Ghost in Hamlet really came out of Purgatorial fires, and whether Athena really descended in her chariot from Olympus and pulled Achilles by his yellow hair when he was in danger of doing something rash?' . Will Durant (1961), p.

499 References. (1961). Rawls, John. External links. (Gutenberg.org). (LibriVox).

(LibriVox). Digitized copy of first edition of The Life of Reason:.:.

George Santayana (Santayana, George, 1863-1952) The Online Books Page Online Books by George Santayana (Santayana, George, 1863-1952) is available, as is a. Santayana, George, 1863-1952: (Gutenberg text). Santayana, George, 1863-1952: The Sense of Beauty: Being the Outlines of Aesthetic Theory (New York et al: Charles Scribner's Sons, c1896). Santayana, George, 1863-1952: (Gutenberg text) - - Additional books from the extended shelves:. Santayana, George, 1863-1952:, also by Henry Herbert Goddard, Henry Herbert Goddard, Henry Herbert Goddard, V.

Anderson, Leland W. Crafts, Clara Harrison Town, Edgar A. Doll, Burton Haseltine, Leroy.

Daniel Moreno Moreno

Telephone operator's voice Thompson, John W. Operators' voices Bradshaw, William.

Speech training for business life Bachrach, Otis Skinner, James Edward McDade, Fred Newton Scott, Shirley M. Voice in singing and speech Gandell, Smiley Blanton, Frederick Bogue Noyes, George B.

Vocal apparatus in health and disease Rice, John Mantle Clapp, Burton Haseltine, Fred Newton Scott, Louise Pound, George F. Individual differences in belief Williamson, W. Pillsbury, Hubert Williams Peet, Edwin Almiron Greenlaw, Thornton Shirley Graves, James Holly Hanford, C. Alphonso Smith, J. Steadman, Albert S. Perkins, Charles Sears Baldwin, Frederick S.

Breed, Frederick S. Breed, Joseph M. Thomas, Joseph M. Thomas, Frederick S. Breed, Jefferson Butler Fletcher, Thomas Percival Beyer, Richard Ray Kirk, Sydney George Fisher, Ronald S. Crane, John Livingston Lowes, Larue. Greek rhetorical language in Puttenham's The arte of English poesie Van Hook, Jefferson Butler Fletcher, Fidelino de Figueiredo, E.

Vaile, Modern Language Association of America, Marshall Field & Company. Speech training in commercial life, and voice and hygiene of the vocal tract Symposium on speech (page images at HathiTrust). Santayana, George, 1863-1952:, also by University of Waterloo.